How does descartes prove that god exists




















In the fifth meditation, Descartes advances a proof for the existence of God using reason alone. Descartes maintains that there are ideas of particular objects or entities in our minds that are demonstrable, yet have not been experienced. What I believe must be considered above all here is the fact that I find within me countless ideas of certain things, that, even if perhaps they do not exist anywhere outside of me, still cannot be said to be nothing.

And although, in a sense, I think them at will, nevertheless they are not something I have fabricated; rather they have their own true and immutable natures.

Descartes Descartes initially uses the concept of a triangle i. Yet this will not be sufficient for Descartes, for we can imagine theoretical entities such as unicorns that we know do not exist. Descartes will have account for the placement of a theoretical concept of a particular entity in the mind and the presence of this entity in the physical or metaphysical world.

The concept of God Descartes is trying to advance is based on the monotheist Christian notion of a supremely perfect being. Most Western intellectual contemporaries of Descartes, whether atheists or believers, were aware of this particular concept of God and would, in all likelihood, not have objected to the advancement of this concept.

In the development of this concept, we are assured that a supreme being lacking in nothing would obviously possess the property of existence. Thus for Descartes, when we think about the essence of God, existence is inseparable. However, Descartes believes that his arguments can proceed without serious difficulty because. Thus it is no less contradictory to think of God that is, a supremely perfect being lacking existence that is, lacking some perfection than it is to think of a mountain without a valley.

This is the crux of the ontological argument for the existence of God. Once we accept the concept of a perfect God, we are unable to rationally deny the existence of that entity. It would be analogous to saying that one understands the concept of a triangle i.

On such an account, Descartes believes that he can make the jump from the conception of God to instantiation of God by direct intuition. This is obviously cognitively suspect. Aware of the possible appearance of sophism, Descartes states:. I can no more think of God as not existing than I can think of a mountain without a valley, nevertheless it surely does not follow from the fact that I think of a mountain without a valley that a mountain exists in the world.

Likewise, from the fact that I think of God as existing, it does not seem to follow that God exists, for my thought imposes no necessity on things. Yet, even with this acknowledgement, Descartes does not see this as a serious problem in continuing. But it is clear from the discussion in section 2 that he had the resources for addressing this objection in a systematic manner. Before examining how Descartes might defend himself, it is important to note that the question at issue is typically framed in non-Cartesian terms and thus often misses its target.

Both Kant and Russell for example are interested in the logical issue of whether existence is a predicate. Descartes, in contrast, was not a logician and disparaged the standard subject-predicate logic inherited from Aristotle.

This intuitive process is psychological in character. It is not a matter of assigning predicates to subjects but of determining whether the idea of a supremely perfect being can be clearly and distinctly perceived while excluding necessary existence from it through a purely intellectual operation.

For him, however, the analogues of properties are clear and distinct ideas and ways of regarding them, not predicates. So, Descartes agrees with Kant that there is no conceptual difference between conceiving of a given substance as actually existing and conceiving it as merely possible. He would, however, stress another conceptual difference that Kant and other critics do not address, namely that between the two grades of existence — contingent and necessary. The clear and distinct ideas of all finite things contain merely contingent or dependent existence, whereas the clear and distinct idea of God uniquely contains necessary or wholly independent existence ibid.

As discussed previously, the ontological argument hinges on this distinction. Another intuition underlying the claim that existence is not a property is that there is more intimate connection between an individual and its existence than the traditional one between a substance and a property, especially if the property in question is conceived as something accidental.

If existence were accidental, then a thing could be without its existence, which seems absurd. It seems no less absurd to say that existence is a property among other properties accidental or essential , for how can a thing even have properties if it does not exist?

Descartes shares this intuition. He does not think that existence is a property in the traditional sense or is even distinct from the substance that is said to bear it. Recall the view discussed in section 2 that there is merely a rational distinction between a substance and its existence, or between the essence and existence of a substance.

This means that the distinction between a substance and its existence is confined to thought or reason. Human beings, in their efforts to understand things using their finite intellects, draw distinctions in thought that do not obtain in reality. In reality, a substance whether created or divine just is its existence. The purpose of this defense of Descartes is not to render a verdict as whether he has the correct account of existence, but to show that he has a rather sophisticated and systematic treatment of what has been one of the great bugbears in the history of philosophy.

He does not make the ad hoc assumption that existence is an attribute in order to serve the needs of the ontological argument. The focus of the debate will then be shifted to the question of who has the correct ontology, rather than whether the ontological argument is sound. The Distinction between Essence and Existence 3.

As Descartes writes in the Fifth Meditation: [1] But if the mere fact that I can produce from my thought the idea of something entails that everything which I clearly and distinctly perceive to belong to that thing really does belong to it, is not this a possible basis for another argument to prove the existence of God?

Certainly, the idea of God, or a supremely perfect being, is one that I find within me just as surely as the idea of any shape or number. And my understanding that it belongs to his nature that he always exists is no less clear and distinct than is the case when I prove of any shape or number that some property belongs to its nature AT ; CSM I clearly and distinctly perceive that necessary existence is contained in the idea of God.

Therefore, God exists. This is evident for example in the version of the ontological argument standardly associated with his name: Version B : I have an idea of supremely perfect being, i.

Necessary existence is a perfection. Therefore, a supremely perfect being exists. It exists by its own power: [2] when we attend to immense power of this being, we shall be unable to think of its existence as possible without also recognizing that it can exist by its own power; and we shall infer from this that this being does really exist and has existed from eternity, since it is quite evident by the natural light that what can exist by its own power always exists.

So we shall come to understand that necessary existence is contained in the idea of a supremely perfect being …. Descartes stresses this point explicitly in the Fifth Meditation, immediately after presenting the two versions of the argument considered above: [3] whatever method of proof I use, I am always brought back to the fact that it is only what I clearly and distinctly perceive that completely convinces me.

Some of the things I clearly and distinctly perceive are obvious to everyone, while others are discovered only by those who look more closely and investigate more carefully; but once they have been discovered, the latter are judged to be just as certain as the former.

In the case of a right-angled triangle, for example, the fact that the square on the hypotenuse is equal to the square on the other two sides is not so readily apparent as the fact that the hypotenuse subtends the largest angle; but once one has seen it, one believes it just as strongly. But as regards God, if I were not overwhelmed by philosophical prejudices, and if the images of things perceived by the senses did not besiege my thought on every side, I would certainly acknowledge him sooner and more easily than anything else.

For what is more manifest than the fact that the supreme being exists, or that God, to whose essence alone existence belongs, exists? AT —69; CSM Here Descartes develops his earlier analogy between the so-called ontological argument and a geometric demonstration.

This debate produced three main positions: The Theory of Real Distinction The Intermediate Position The Theory of Rational Distinction Proponents of the first view conceived the distinction between essence and existence as obtaining between two separate things.

Descartes reaffirms this conclusion in a letter intended to elucidate his account of the relation between essence and existence: [4]… existence, duration, size, number and all universals are not, it seems to me, modes in the strict sense …. They are referred to by a broader term and called attributes … because we do indeed understand the essence of a thing in one way when we consider it in abstraction from whether it exists or not, and in a different way when we consider it as existing; but the thing itself cannot be outside our thought without its existence ….

Accordingly I say that shape and other similar modes are strictly speaking modally distinct from the substance whose modes they are; but there is a lesser distinction between the other attributes …. I call it a rational distinction ….

To an unknown correspondent, AT ; CSMK Indications are given here as to how a rational distinction is produced in our thought. In a few important passages, Descartes affirms that existence is contained in the clear and distinct idea of every single thing, but he also insists that there are different grades of existence: [5] Existence is contained in the idea or concept of every single thing, since we cannot conceive of anything except as existing.

Possible or contingent existence is contained in the concept of a limited thing, whereas necessary and perfect existence is contained in the concept of a supremely perfect being Axiom 10, Second Replies; AT ; CSM Johannes Caterus, the author of the First Set of Objections to the Meditations , puts the point as follows: [6] Even if it is granted that a supremely perfect being carries the implication of existence in virtue of its very title, it still does not follow that the existence in question is anything actual in the real world; all that follows is that the concept of existence is inseparably linked to the concept of a supreme being.

So you cannot infer that the existence of God is anything actual unless you suppose that the supreme being actually exists; for then it will actually contain all perfections, including the perfection of real existence AT ; CSM Descartes responds to this criticism as follows: [7] For as far as our concepts are concerned there is no impossibility in the nature of God; on the contrary, all the attributes which we include in the concept of the divine nature are so interconnected that it seems to us to be self-contradictory that any one of them should not belong to God AT ; CSM Oeuvres de Descartes , vols.

I-XII, revised edition. Paris: J. The Philosophical Writings of Descartes , vols. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. References to this work are by volume and page, separated by a colon. Critique of Pure Reason , trans. Norman Kemp Smith. London: Macmillan Education Ltd. Abbruzzese, John Edward, Adams, Robert, Barnes, Jonathan, The Ontological Argument , London: Macmillan. Beyssade, Jean-Marie, Chappell, Vere, Cottingham, John, Descartes , Oxford: Blackwell.

Cress, Donald, Crocker, Sylvia Fleming, Curley, Edwin, Mercer and E. Doney, Willis, Dougherty, M. Dutton, Blake, Edelberg, Walter, Forgie, J.

William, Gaukroger, Stephen, Gueroult, Martial, Harrelson, Kevin, Hartshorne, Charles, Kenny, Anthony, Koistinen, Olli, Newman, Lex, and Alan Nelson, Nolan, Lawrence and Alan Nelson, Nolan, Lawrence, Oppenheimer, Paul, and Zalta, Edward.

Tomberlin ed. Oppy, Graham, Plantinga, Alvin ed. Secada, Jorge, Cartesian Metaphysics , Cambridge University Press. Further, Descartes realizes that he is less formally real than the objective reality of perfection and therefore there has to be a perfect being existing formally from whom his innate idea of a perfect being derives wherein he could have created the ideas of all substances, but not the one of God. The second proof then goes on to question who it is then that keeps him — having an idea of a perfect being — in existence, eliminating the possibility that he himself would be able to do.

He proves this by saying that he would owe it to himself, if he were his own existence maker, to have given himself all sorts of perfections. The very fact that he is not perfect means he would not bear his own existence. Similarly, his parents, who are also imperfect beings, could not be the cause of his existence since they could not have created the idea of perfection within him.

That leaves only a perfect being, God, that would have had to exist to create and be constantly recreating him. Essentially, Descartes' proofs rely on the belief that by existing, and being born an imperfect being but with a soul or spirit , one must, therefore, accept that something of more formal reality than ourselves must have created us.

Basically, because we exist and are able to think ideas, something must have created us. Actively scan device characteristics for identification. Use precise geolocation data. Select personalised content. Create a personalised content profile. Measure ad performance. Select basic ads. Create a personalised ads profile. Select personalised ads. Apply market research to generate audience insights. Measure content performance. Develop and improve products. List of Partners vendors.

Share Flipboard Email. Andrea Borghini.



0コメント

  • 1000 / 1000